Monday, June 3, 2019

Goodness As A Simple And Indefinable Property Philosophy Essay

Goodness As A Simple And Indefinable Property Philosophy EssayMoores Principia Ehica was the first to claim that greatness is an abominable non-natural attribute belonging to a simple intuition. For Moore a property is natural if, and unaccompanied if, it is detectable by the senses1. Ever since Moore, the debate of what good is has become of the essence(p) to moral philosophy and meta ethics.Moore, to understand the simple notion of good, puts forth an analogy of the simple notion of yellow. The notion of yellow back tooth only be conceived by those who already understand it, the same applies to good. Moore is contrasting the indefinable understanding of goodness to the indefinable perception of a colors qualia. Qualia is correctd as the subjective persona of conscious experience2. We john mention certain properties of yellow its specific wavelength or frequency. But we cannot mention what the nature of the property of world yellow is. This is because colour is a simple pro perty that cannot be analyzed. To experience colour, we must appeal to our experience.Complex notions, on the other hand, can be be by their sub-parts and the relationships between those sub-parts. The property of being a horse is an example of a confused object that can be setd because it has many different qualities3. But it can only be defined until it has been reduced to its simplest terms beyond which those simple terms cannot be defined. Since simple terms cannot be reduced any further, they cannot be gauzy to anyone who does not already understand them. Yellow and good are not complex, but are simple notions. Moore, in this sense, thinks good is indefinable.Good, as a pattern does not correspond to the concepts of pleasure, desire or usefulness. Given that there are things that we wawl satisfying as well as good, but we can call a thing refreshing, desirable or useful and thusly ask, but is it good? The fact that we are able to ask such a misgiving of a thing with p articular qualities of pleasure, desire or usefulness is evidence, for Moore, that good cannot be identical to the concepts of pleasure, desire or usefulness. This is known as the open-ended scruple problem. Saying that something is pleasurable does not exclude the question, yes, but is it good?The Open Question ArgumentMoore backs his claim that good is simple and indefinable through the illustrious open question argument. He argues that good cannot be defined by considering the fact that whatever definition be offered, it may be always asked, with significance, of the complex so defined, whether it is itself good 4. What he means by this argument is that, if we, for instance, equate good with doing what is pleasurable (which seems reasonable) then, Moore points out, that it can still be asked is it good to do what is pleasurable? Therefore, it remains an open question (hence the name of the argument) whether something is good, irrespective of it being pleasurable.Moore accepts t hat the argument does not demonstrate that pleasure is not the only test for an actions goodness, all it demonstrates is that what is pleasurable cannot be known by simply inspecting the definition of good. What is good has to be known in another way.Moore also formulates the term naturalistic phantasm. Naturalistic fallacy is defined as an intent to classify some things simply being the case to the case of it being good. If something is pleasurable then, this quality alone cannot tell us anything about its being good.The Naturalistic FallacyAccording to Moore, if good is simple, indefinable, cannot be analyzed and what is good? remains and open question then an attempt to define the simple notion of good as any other naturalistic notion is to commit the naturalistic fallacy5. To clarify, Moore draws the yellow analogy. Yellow can be defined as a specific wave length but these waves are not yellow.To commit the naturalistic fallacy is a common mistake when attempting to define good . While it may be entirely possible that all things that are good can also be something else, just as yellow things engender certain other properties, but to equate these properties to the definition of good is incorrect.Good as an intuitionMoore claims that though good is indefinable, it is part of our everyday coherent language. This is because we bring out good based on our intuition. MacIntyre objects to this view by saying, how, then, do we recognise the intrinsically good? The only answer Moore offers is that we just do 6. But this would hasten good a complex notion since for different people good would have different analyzable content. Furthermore, this would be contrary to Moores claim of good being a simple notion.ObjectionsPhilosophers such as Mackie, MacIntyre and Nagel do not essentially agree with the naturalistic fallacy or the validity of the open question argument.Mackie, presents an remonstration to Moore with his argument from queerness. He argues that there i s no such thing as goodness and badness. Moreover, he claims, goodness and badness have no properties or qualities that can be reduced to simpler terms since they do not exist. Goodness and badness are meant to properties of objects but they are queerly different to other properties like weight, coat or fabric. Mackie concludes that goodness and badness are prescriptive moral terms and intrinsic or inherent properties of things is simply not possible.7Moore responds by arguing that good is a simple concept of ethics. And all other ethical concepts must be derived from it. Although good cannot be defined, what is good can be defined. Thus, while we do not know the definition of good we can identify which things are good. David Hume says it best, just because something is the case does not by that fact indicate to us that it ought to be the case. ConclusionIn my opinion, Moores claim of good being indefinable due to it being a simple and non natural property is an extreme argument to make. If Moore is right, then it would mean that there is no objective way of defining good and that the term is relative to the clement species. This fact is hard to reconcile. There would be red-blooded implications for the way good is discussed at a practical and theoretical level of ethics.Many do not agree with Moores arguments, especially MacIntyre who says, more unwarranted and unwarranted assertions are perhaps made in Principia Ethica than in any other single book of moral philosophy 8. But we have to accept that Moore has been trustworthy for raising many issue that have become central to meta ethics today.On the other hand, maybe good is so inherent and intrinsic to the human mind that we cannot completely define it. This would not be surprising as our language is not a rational or precise tool that can be used to comprehensively define one of the most important terms used in ethical discussions today.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.